A Review of the Linguistic Research on Definite Descriptions
更新时间:2023-04-15 05:05:01 阅读量: 实用文档 文档下载
- 阿根廷推荐度:
- 相关推荐
A Review of the Linguistic Research on Definite Descriptions
Renata Vieira
1.Introduction
We present in this paper a review on the linguistic literature on the types of uses of definite descriptions (noun phrases with the definite article the). Definite descriptions have been studied extensively by linguists, philosophers, psychologists, and computational linguists. The theories discussed in this paper help us to understand the problem of interpreting definite descriptions. We look at research studying the various ways in which definite descriptions relate to their antecedents and/or to the context. We compare terms referring to the various types of uses of definite descriptions by presenting tables that relate examples of definite description use to different terminology, according to different authors.
This review is mainly motivated by the necessity of understanding the role of definite descriptions for co-reference processing. Co-reference processing has been one main issue in natural language processing, artificial intelligence and computational linguists. It has direct applications in the field of information extraction. Much work has been done in anaphora resolution, and usually definite descriptions are considered as a special case of anaphora and their treatment is included in general frameworks that mainly deal with pronouns. The work presented here aims to provide a concise material reviewing several works on the use of definite descriptions revealing the complexity of the problem, which we believe to deserve a particular treatment of its own.
2. Hawkins' descriptive list of the uses of the definite article
The wide range of uses of definite descriptions was already highlighted in (Christopherson, 1939). In the third chapter of his book, Hawkins (1978) further develops and extends Christopherson's descriptive analysis. According to Hawkins, the definite article may be used on the basis of a discourse antecedent (anaphoric and associative anaphoric uses) as well as independently from the previous discourse (situational, unfamiliar with explanatory modifiers and unexplanatory modifier uses). We present below Hawkins' taxonomy. The examples are often repeated from or similar to those in (Hawkins, 1978).
Anaphoric Use
These are definite descriptions that refer back to an antecedent in the discourse (both description and antecedent evoke the same entity).
1.
(a) Fred was discussing an interesting book in his class. I went to discuss the book with him afterwards.
(b) Fred was wearing trousers. The pants had a big patch on them.
(c) Bill was working at a lathe the other day. All of a sudden the machine stopped turning.
(d) Mary travelled to Paris. The journey lasted six hours.
(e) A man and a woman entered restaurant. The couple was received by a waiter.
As seen in the examples, a definite description may use the same descriptive predicate as its antecedent, or any other capable of indicating the same antecedent (e.g., a synonym, a hyponym, a nominalization, summation, etc.).
Associative Anaphoric Use
Speaker and hearer may have (shared) knowledge of the relations between certain objects evoked by the discourse (the triggers) and their components or attributes (the associates): associative anaphoric uses of definite descriptions exploit this knowledge.
2.
(a) Bill drove past our house in a car. The exhaust fumes were terrible.
(b) Bill bought a new car to please Mary but she didn't like the colour.
(c) Fred was discussing an interesting book in his class. He knows the author.
(d) I went to a wedding last weekend. The bride was a friend of mine. She baked the cake herself.
Immediate Situation Use
The next two uses of definite descriptions identified by Hawkins are used to refer to an object in the situation of utterance. The referent may be visible, or its presence may be inferred.
Visible situation use This type of use occurs when the object referred to is visible to both speaker and hearer, as in the following examples:
3.
(a) Please, pass me the salt.
(b) Put it on the table.
Immediate situation use These are definite descriptions whose referent is a constituent of the immediate situation in which the use of the definite description is located, without necessarily being visible. This use is commonly found in notices such as:
4.
(a) Beware of the dog.
(b) Don't feed the pony.
At the same time the hearer is informed of the existence of these objects, he is also being instructed to use the immediate situation of utterance to determine which dog or pony is meant.
Larger Situation Uses
Hawkins lists two classes of definite descriptions that are used in situations in which the speaker appeals to the hearer's knowledge of entities existing in the non-immediate or larger situation of utterance---knowledge they share by being members of the same community,
for instance. Whereas in associative anaphoric uses the trigger is a NP introduced in the discourse, in larger situation uses the trigger is the situation itself.
Specific knowledge in the larger situation This is the case in which both the speaker and the hearer know about the existence of the referent, as in the example below, in which it is assumed that speaker and hearer are both inhabitants of Halifax, a town which has a gibbet at the top of Gibbet Street:
5. The Gibbet no longer stands.
General knowledge in the larger situation use Specific knowledge is not a necessary part of the meaning of definite descriptions in larger situation uses. While some hearers may have specific knowledge about the actual inpiduals referred to by a definite description, others may not. General knowledge about the existence of certain types of objects in certain types of situations is sufficient. An example is the following utterance in the context of a wedding (as first utterance between two people):
6. Have you seen the bridesmaids?
Such a first mention of the bridesmaids is possible on the basis of the knowledge that weddings typically have bridesmaids. In the same way, a first mention of the bride, the church service, or the best man would be possible. Note, however, that background knowledge may be different from inpidual to inpidual: one hearer might rely on his specific knowledge of a particular referent to interpret a description, whereas the other relies on his general knowledge to interpret the same description.
Unfamiliar Uses with Explanatory Modifiers
Hawkins classifies as unfamiliar those definite descriptions that are not anaphoric, do not rely on information about the situation of utterance, and are not associates of some trigger in the previous discourse. Hawkins groups these definite descriptions in classes according to their syntactic and lexical properties, as follows.
NP complements One form of unfamiliar definite descriptions is characterised by the presence of a complement to the head noun.
7.
(a) Bill is amazed by the fact that there is so much life on Earth.
(b) The philosophical aphasic came to the conclusion that language did not exist.
(c) Fleet Street has been buzzing with the rumour that the Prime Minister is going to resign.
(d) I remember the time when I was a little girl.
Nominal modifiers The presence of a nominal modifier is, according to Hawkins, the distinguishing feature of these phrases.
8.
(a) I don't like the colour red.
(b) The number seven is my lucky number.
Referent establishing relative clauses Relative clauses may establish a referent for the hearer without a previous mention, when the relative clause refers to something mutually known.
9.
(a) What's wrong with Bill? Oh, the woman he went out with last night was nasty to him. (But: ?? Oh, the woman was nasty to him.)
(b) ...the box (that is) over there.
Associative clauses Associative clauses incorporate both the trigger and the associate of an associative anaphoric sequence. The modifiers of the head noun specify the referent with which the definite description is associated.
10.
(a) I remember the beginning of the war very well.
(b) There was a funny story on the front page of the Guardian this morning.
(c) ... the bottom of the sea.
(d) ... the fight during the war.
The syntactic structure of a definite description does not guarantee that it is unfamiliar. Unexplanatory Modifiers Use
Finally, Hawkins lists a small number of modifiers (that he calls unexplanatory) which require the use of the definite article:
11.
(a) My wife and I share the same secrets.
(b) The first person to sail to America was an Icelander.
(c) The fastest person to sail to America ...
There is nothing in the modifier that informs the hearer what is being referred to; Hawkins says that in the first of the examples above the definite points merely to an identity between two sets of secrets.
3. Prince’s theory of familiarity
Prince studied in detail the connection between the speaker/writer's and hearer/reader's assumptions about each other and the linguistic realisation of noun phrases (Prince, 1981; Prince, 1992). Although she studies noun phrases in general, the taxonomy she proposes has proved equally useful for our analysis of definite descriptions in particular. What is original and especially interesting in Prince’s work is the important distinction between two kinds of familiarity, a distinction not explicitly observed in Hawkins’ theory. She distinguishes between discourse and hearer familiarity, as seen below.
Hearer new / Hearer old
One factor affecting the choice of a noun phrase, according to Prince, is whether a discourse entity is old or new with respect to the hearer’s knowledge. Typically, a speaker will use a
proper name or a definite description when he or she assumes that the addressee already knows the entity whom the speaker is referring to, as in:
12.I'm waiting for it to be noon so I can call Sandy Thompson.
O n the other hand, if the speaker believes that the addressee does not know of Sandy Thompson, in general, an indefinite will be used:
13.I'm waiting for it to be noon so I can call someone in California.
D iscourse entities can also be new or old with respect to the discourse model.
D iscourse new / Discourse old
A ccording to Prince, a NP may refer to an entity that has already been `evoked' in the current discourse (textually evoked), or it may evoke an entity which has not been previously mentioned (situationally evoked, unused, inferrable, containing inferrable, brand new). “Discourse novelty” is distinct from “hearer novelty”: both Sandy Thompson and someone in California mentioned above may well be discourse new even if only the second one will be hearer new. On the other hand, for an entity being discourse old entails it being hearer old. As pointed out by Prince, the distinction between containing inferrable and unused is sometimes ambiguous: what is unused for one reader may be containing inferrable for another, depending on their inpidual knowledge background.
P rince criticises the traditional binary distinction between “given” and “new” discourse entities as too simplistic, and proposes a much more detailed taxonomy of “givenness”---or, as she calls it, assumed familiarity---meant to address this problem.
A ssumed Familiarity
B rand-new A NP may introduce an entity which is both discourse and hearer new. Brand new entities are usually introduced by indefinites, such as someone in California in the example above.
B rand new anchored A new entity is anchored, according to Prince, if it is linked to another discourse entity, this link is contained in the NP representing the entity and this link is not itself new. An example is: A guy I work with... Prince seems to be considering only indefinites in this class, but a definite such as the guys I work with could perhaps be regarded as brand new anchored in the same sense. There are also some definite descriptions that describe new entities and are linked to entities that are new, as in the footsteps of a yeti. Their place in Prince’s framework is not clear.
E voked NPs may invoke situationally evoked or textually evoked entities. Only textually evoked entities are discourse old. Situationally evoked entities correspond to Hawkins' visible/immediate situation use.
U nused NPs may evoke hearer old but discourse new entities. Unused NPs describe entities that are known to the speaker/hearer but which haven’t been mentioned (used) previously in
the discourse. These are like those cases called by Hawkins larger situation/specific knowledge.
I nferrable Some discourse entities are not discourse old or even hearer old, but they are not entirely new, either. Hawkins called such uses of definite descriptions associative anaphoric: a book, the author. Prince called such entities inferrables. Prince did not introduce a class for those entities which are inferrable from the situation (Hawkins' larger situation/general knowledge); they will be referred to later as situationally inferrable.
C ontaining inferrable Prince proposes a category for entities, which are like inferrables, but whose connection with previous hearer's knowledge is specified as part of the NP itself. Her example the door of the Bastille in the example below.
14.The door of the Bastille was painted purple.
A t least three of the unfamiliar uses of Hawkins--NP complements, referent-establishing relative clauses, and associative clauses--fall in this category. As pointed out by Prince, the distinction between containing inferrable and unused is sometimes ambiguous: what is unused for one reader may be containing inferrable for another, depending on their inpidual knowledge background.
4. L?bner’s theory
L?bner (L?bner, 1985) observes that the interpretation of descriptions may depend on arguments and attributes given in the referring act itself or by the immediate situation, and not only on textual antecedents. He takes descriptions to be terms like proper names. L?bner adopts Christopherson's (1939) view according to which the fundamental property of definite NPs is that they refer unambiguously. L?bner claims that the definite article indicates that the noun is to be taken as a functional concept (FC). This idea is based on the distinction between sortal and relational nouns: sortal nouns identify a class (woman), while relational nouns describe objects as standing in a certain relation to others (wife). Functional nouns are a subclass of relational nouns. Functions relate objects unambiguously (one to one) to others: they assign values to arguments. Functional concepts identify a referent when the situation and proper arguments are given. L?bner’s classificatory scheme is based on the distinction between semantic and pragmatic definites. Semantic definites are those cases in which the interpretation is independent of the utterance's previous discourse or immediate context of utterance; the general situation, however, is always an argument1. The semantic definites L?bner lists correspond to Hawkins' larger situation and unfamiliar uses. Pragmatic definites, on the other hand, are essentially dependent on the particular context of utterance for their non-ambiguous interpretation.
S emantic Definites
1This argument relates the description to the location, time and circumstances of the utterance.
L?bner defines a semantic definite as a NP denoting a functional concept. According to the number of arguments definites take, they are classified into FC1s, FC2s and FC3s. All of them involve the general situation as one of their arguments, often implicitly.
S emantic FC1s These semantic definites are concepts for objects that play a unique role in a given situation. This class includes:
a) proper names;
b) sortal nouns followed by a proper name of some sort;
c) cases in which a subordinate clause specifies an abstract sortal head as FC1s;
d) combinations of certain adjectival attributes (superlatives, ordinals, as well as next, last, only, etc.) with sortal or relational nouns forming a complex FC1; and
e) those cases called simple FC1s which are dependent on temporal and spatial location.
E xamples of each type are shown below:
15.
a)the Empire State Building, the London Symphony Orchestra;
b)the year 1984, the word “the”, the opera Rigoletto;
c)the rumour that Reagan is going to resign, the dream to become rich;
d)the next/last/third president of the association;
e)the weather, the time, the air, the moon.
All these definite descriptions yield functional concepts. They always take one argument relative to the given situation. These concepts assign a functional value to situations. Descriptions such as the sun, the moon, the Earth assign the same value to a wide range of locations and time. For other descriptions the referents or values are more locally determined: the weather, the atmosphere. Proper names usually apply to a certain referent relatively to a domain of situations. A name like Paul is dependent on the social circumstances for its unambiguous interpretation. In many languages personal names are used with the definite article. They name something unambiguously which may not have been mentioned before; hearers do not need to find this named entity in the immediate context. These descriptions correspond to some of Hawkins' larger situation and unfamiliar uses.
Semantic FC2s with explicit arguments Generally an FC2 is connected to its second argument by a possessive relation (in the sense that something or someone has something). These cases syntactically consist of a definite article which precedes a complex expression containing the FC2 noun and a PP of the form of NP, as the examples below. A FC2 results in a FC1 when complemented with its argument. L?bner notes that the number of arguments referring to the situation may in fact vary: compare, for instance, descriptions such as the price of an apartment, the price of an apartment in Korea, the price of an apartment in Korea in the eighties.
16.
a)the president of the U.S.;
b)the meaning of the definite article.
Semantic FC2s with implicit arguments These descriptions depend on the immediate physical environment, which functions as an implicit deictic argument. Hawkins’introductory situational uses fall in this category.
17. This is the clutch.
I n the example above, the argument is a car in the immediate physical environment. Another example of implicit deictic FC2 is Hawkins’ larger situation use based on general knowledge:
18.The Prime Minister has resigned.
T he location of the utterance is included in the territory of a state to which the description refers (indirectly). L?bner also includes in this class those expressions that refer indirectly to referents previously introduced in the discourse, such as a book... the author, referring to them as FC2s with implicit anaphoric argument. (These cases correspond to Hawkins' associative anaphoric uses.) L?bner states that the crucial condition under which FC2s with implicit arguments are possible is that the head noun in these uses provides a two-place functional concept for which there is an appropriate argument in the immediate context (physical or linguistic). In (L?bner, 1996) it is claimed that the semantic/thematic roles of verbs are also FC2s. For every reading event, he says, there is the role of the reader and the role of the read; underlying theses roles are the functional concepts the reader of this reading event, and what is read in this reading event. Further roles may be connected to a reading event, such as medium, time, location, speed and others. In this later paper L?bner adopts a frame-like semantic network to explain FC2s with implicit anaphoric argument.
S emantic FC3s In these cases the definite article precedes a noun that is complemented with two arguments.
19. the distance between A and B
P ragmatic Definites
P ragmatic definites have non-functional head nouns (notice that it is the use, not the noun itself, that is relational or sortal) and thus depend on the particular situation or immediate context for unambiguous reference. They are pided in anaphoric, endophoric and deictic uses.
A naphoric These descriptions are resolved to a previously introduced referent (as in a book... the book). Hawkins’ anaphoric uses fall in this category.
E ndophoric (cataphoric) These definites have relational or sortal head nouns with disambiguating attributes, as in the example below. Hawkins classifies this use as unfamiliar with referent establishing relative clauses.
20.the woman Bill went out with last night
Deictic These uses refer to the immediate context, and correspond to Hawkins' immediate situation uses.
5. Fraurud′s study of first mention and subsequent uses
F raurud (1990) presents a corpus-based study of definite NPs use in Swedish distributed between the following text types: brochures, newspapers, textbooks and debate books (all professional, non-fiction prose, and based on a binary classification scheme: Subsequent mention: (corresponding to Hawkins' anaphoric definite descriptions and Prince's discourse old), and
First mention: including all other definite descriptions.
Fraurud's notion of subsequent mention is defined in terms of co-referentiality (NPs referring to the same entity). She notes that a NP that is co-referent with another NP is not necessarily anaphoric. The interpretation of an anaphor is crucially dependent on the identification of a discourse referent introduced by an antecedent (as is usually the case for pronouns); whereas co-referentiality only implies that a discourse referent previously mentioned in the discourse is evoked by an NP, but the NP's interpretation need not to be essentially dependent on this previous mention (as for subsequent mention of proper names). Fraurud's simplified taxonomy is due to the fact that she was primarily interested in verifying the empirical basis for the claim that indefinite NPs trigger the establishment of a new discourse referent in a discourse model while definite NPs trigger the search for or the retrieval of a prior discourse referent. She recognises that the existence of first mention definite NPs is acknowledged in the literature, but criticises the fact that they tend to be treated as secondary relative to the anaphoric use of definite NPs, giving as example Heim's File Change Semantics (discussed earlier). In her study Fraurud observes that only 34.8% of initial mention NPs were actually indefinites, and of all indefinites, only 9.4% were referred back to. She points to the problem for NP processing of having a vast number of entities made available for anaphoric reference and just a small portion being referred to. But perhaps the most interesting result is the large proportion of definite NPs in first mention uses found in her corpus: 60.9%. Also interesting is Fraurud's observation about the syntactic complexity of first mention definite NPs. She claims that genitive/possessive constructions of the form the X's Y or the Y of X, postposed prepositional phrases, and restrictive adjectival modifiers make the NP “self-contained”. These NPs, as L?bner's FC2s, explicitly sign their relation to other referents; and therefore, one would expect that complex definites be more often used as first than subsequent mention. And in fact, 75% of the complex definite NPs in her corpus were first mention.
6. Clark's bridging references
Clark’s paper “Bridging” (1977) is concerned with the construction of implicatures as part of the process of comprehension (understood as the computation of an antecedent). He identifies the possible semantic relations between the referring expression and its antecedent. Clark is only concerned with implicatures derived from textual relations, which correspond to Hawkins’ anaphoric and associative anaphoric uses. The distinctions he made are reviewed here for the specific case of definite descriptions.
Direct reference
Clark notes that a description often makes direct reference to previously mentioned objects, events or states.
Identity Examples given for this class are:
21.
a)I met a man. The man told me a story.
b)I ran two miles. The run did me good.
He also gives as an example of direct reference (identity) the following:
22.Her house was large. The size surprised me.
I n (24) shown above, the term “direct” refers to the fact that the size (of the house) has already been mentioned (when describing it as being large). This notion of “identity” does not seem to conform to a notion of co-referentiality. In other approaches (see Strand, below, for instance) the reference the size is seen as associated to the noun the house rather than to the adjective large.
P ronominalization s These are cases in which the description uses only a subset of the properties that characterise a previously mentioned entity. We have a continuum: an elderly gentleman, the elderly gentleman, the elderly man, the gentleman, the man, the oldster, the adult, the person, he. The semantic relations of synonymy and hypernymy belong to this class together with the use of pronouns.
23.I met an elderly gentleman. The man told me a story.
E pithets This class contains those cases in which the bridging reference adds new information to the entity referred to.
24.I met a man. The bastard stole my money.
I n the example above (26) the antecedent for the bastard is the entity referred to by a man---that entity is also a bastard, but this information is new. The extra information is concerned with the speaker's opinion of the facts rather than the facts themselves.
S et membership In this class are those cases in which the description picks out an element from a previously mentioned set.
25.
a)I met two people. The woman told me a story.
b)I swung three times. The first swing missed by a mile.
Indirect reference by association
Clark, like the other authors we have discussed, notes that the description may not have a directly mentioned antecedent but one that is closely related to it. He notes that the associated information varies in its predictability from absolutely necessary to quite unnecessary, distinguishing three levels:
Necessary parts
26.
a)I entered the room. The ceiling was high.
I entered the room. The size was overwhelming.
Probable parts
27.
a)I entered the room. The windows looked out to the bay.
b)I went shopping. The walk did me good.
Inducible parts
28.I entered the room. The chandeliers sparkled brightly.
I ndirect reference by characterisation
A description may characterise a role played in an event or circumstance mentioned earlier. Clark presents a variety of such cases:
N ecessary roles
29.
a)John was murdered. The murderer got away.
b)I went shopping. The time I started was 3 p.m.
Optional roles
30.
a)John died. The murderer got away.
b)John was murdered. The knife lay nearby.
Clark observes that often noun phrases contain as part of their specification the information of how they relate to other events as in the person who murdered John, the knife with which it was done. Adjectives can carry out a characterising function too, as in the guilty party got away. He says that what adjectives, relative clauses and derived nouns (such as murderer) do is to pick out the role the intended antecedent plays in the previously mentioned events. Clark comments that sometimes the distinctions between parts and roles may be impossible to maintain.
Relations of reasons, causes and consequences As we have already seen, the antecedent of a bridging description is often an event and not an object and may give the reason for, cause of, or consequence of other events or states. Clark's examples for this class do not include the use of definite descriptions. We present as an example (33).
31.An earthquake... The suffering people are going through...
7. Sidner’s co-specification and specification rules
Sidner (1979) lists several ways (rules) in which a full definite NP may derive its co-specification or specification from the focus (a list of the most salient elements in the discourse, i.e., what the discourse is about). The focus for definite description interpretation includes:
the current focus, the most salient element in the last sentence according to a set of rules proposed by Sidner;
the potential focus, elements in the last sentence other than the current focus;
the stacked focus, the set of current foci previous to the last sentence (It is not clear if the Actor Focus Stack should be also considered for definite description interpretation.). Sidner presents several algorithms that work together to resolve anaphoric NPs and to keep track of the discourse focus. Her algorithms rely on a semantic network that encodes elements and their associations, provides links expressing their general class, and provides for inheritance of associations. The rules listed by Sidner are the following: Explicit Backwards Co-specification
Co-specification 1 Definite description and focus have the same head and no new information is introduced by the definite.
32.A small office... The office
S he mentions the difficulty imposed by definites with new information since it is not clear whether they co-specify with the focus or refer to a new discourse element. Clark, however, has observed that a definite description may specify or add new information to the antecedent (epithet).
C o-specification 2 The definite's head noun lexically generalises that of the focus and has no restrictive postmodifiers.
33. A ferret... The animal...
S he claims that generalisations accompanied by restrictive relative post-nominal modifiers fail to co-specify with the focus. This class is similar to Clark's pronominalization.
I mplicit Backwards Specification
H ere the definite does not co-specify with the focus. It is said, instead, to specify an element c losely related to the focus by association. She proposes the following restriction on the elements available for the computation of specifications: NPs in the stacked foci are not considered as focus for these cases. Sidner says that stacked foci do not seem to be used in this way perhaps because the additional processing time would not make it possible to extend the judgements to the focus stack. This means that a definite description can only specify an element in the previous sentence.
A ssociated Specification The definite names an entity associated with the focus directly or by inheritance on the network hierarchy. The inferences made in the association involve common sense knowledge about the world.
34.Meeting... The participants...
I nferred Specification As above but the inferences involve hearers' suppositions that are not necessarily true. (This class may include a broad range of relations.)
35.The dead heiress... The murderer
S et-element Specification The focus is a set, the description is singular and has the same head as the focus and additional modifiers whose role is to determine which member of the set is being discussed.
36.There were clowns performing in the square. The clown with the unicycle did a
fantastic stunt.
S idner comments that these cases are easier to distinguish than other specifications, because the head noun is the singular form of the noun phrase represented in the focus. There are, however, set-element sequences such as a couple...the woman which would involve knowledge of set-element relations as well as generalisation and/or associations. It is not clear whether the associated specification or inferred specification rules would handle cases like this.
C omputed Specification The specification of the description may be computed from that of the focus. The description has an ordinal modifier, the same head as the focus and no relative clause modifiers. Sidner observes that descriptions containing full relatives (such as the first person to sail to America) use the relative clause and not the focus to compute its specification.
37.A meeting... The last meeting but two
W ith the restrictions she imposes, Sidner misses cases like A conference ... the first talk, or C lark's example I swung three times. The first swing... Again, it is not clear if these would be cases treated by the rules of associated or inferred specification. When no relation can be established, Sidner says that definite NPs with no modifiers are odd uses. For those descriptions that have modifiers she says that they specify outside the discourse context.
8. Strand's taxonomy of linking relations
S trand's approach (Strand, 1996) is also mainly concerned with those cases of definite description use in which an explicit contextual relation (link) holds between the description and an antecedent (anchor). Strand, as Sidner, assumes the availability of a semantic representation of the text (in this case, DRT) and inference mechanisms. He proposes taxonomy of linking relations in which five main classes are distinguished along with fifteen subclasses. They are as follows:
C o-referentiality
T he antecedent and definite refer to the same entity through identical or different description.
I dentical head The anchor and the definite description share the same head noun
38.A yellow car... The car...
G eneralization The definite description is more general than or is a synonymous of the antecedent.
39.A car... The vehicle...
S pecification The description is more specific than the antecedent.
40.A car... The sedan...
R edescription The definite description is a fully alternative description of the antecedent which neither entails nor is entailed by any conditions on (properties of) the antecedent. 41.A car... The notorious wreck...
S trand's co-referential class differs from Clark's direct reference. Whereas Clark classifies the house was large... The size surprised me as direct reference, Strand does not. Other differences in their taxonomies are discussed below.
N arrowing
T he definite is part/member or an argument/role of the antecedent.
S et-member The description is a member or a subset of the set indicated by the antecedent.
42.A school class... The girls...
W hole-part The description constitutes a part of its antecedent.
43.A car... The engine...
E vent-argument The description is an argument of an antecedent event.
44.John was murdered. The murderer...
W idening
T hese are cases which expand on familiar sets.
M ember-set The description is a set of which the antecedent is a member or a subset.
45.John and his nephew... The family...
P art-whole The description has the antecedent as its part.
46.A wall... The building...
Adjoining
P art-part The antecedent and description are members of the same state or parts of the same whole.
512f4f2f7375a417866f8f19st Wednesday... The next day...
P ossessor-thing The antecedent possesses the description.
48.A professor... The car...
D elimitation
I n these cases the anchor may be seen as an argument to the description.
A rgument-event The description is an event in which the antecedent is an argument delimiting its denotation.
49.Israel and Egypt... The peace agreement...
S ubcategorization The description subcategorizes for something of the antecedent’s type. This applies to so called relational nouns like father, weight, price, owner, driver, etc. 50.A bicycle... The price...
T ime-anchored The time region indicated by the antecedent gives a more delimited or unambiguous reading to the description.
512f4f2f7375a417866f8f19st Wednesday... The news...
S pace-anchored The space region indicated by the antecedent delimits the description. 52.A Greek village... The taxi drivers...
S trand also mentions the existence of implicit or inferred anchors: for instance, when someone is telling about a visit to a Greek village, the (implicit) time of visit may be an anchor to the referents of the descriptions.
S trand acknowledges the problem of multiple anchors/links being available for a description resolution. He says that one should give preference to the most informative link and that identity should be preferred whenever possible. However, besides the problem of deciding between identity and non-identity, it seems hard to find a way of identifying a `most informative' link. Strand mentions that an opposite approach is one like Sidner's, where a saliency order is followed.
11. Comparison of terminology
I n this section we compare the classifications presented in the previous sections. We present tables which relate examples of definite description use with the classes identified by the authors we have discussed. Tables 1 (a and b) and 2 (a, b, c and d) describe the anaphoric and associative uses respectively. Seven different schemes are listed (Hawkins, 1878; Prince, 1992; Fraurud, 1990, L?bner, 1985; Clark, 1977; Sidner, 1979; Strand, 1997). The other tables (Tables 3 and 4) consider only four of the authors, since not all authors refer to the phenomena presented there (situational and unfamiliar uses). Although Sidner notices that definite descriptions may specify outside the linguistic context, she does not explain in which different ways. Strand briefly mentions the existence of implicit and inferred anchors. Clark is only concerned with discourse relations. The terms that
appear in the tables in Italics are our guesses for the examples not explicitly discussed by the author of the corresponding scheme. Question marks were placed where the authors were generally silent about the case, and it was not clear whether their classification would apply or not to the example. We can see that those authors who present a more comprehensive characterisation of uses of definite descriptions (Hawkins, Prince, Fraurud and L?bner) do not discriminate anaphoric and associative descriptions in as much detail as the others (Clark, Sidner and Strand) do. On the other hand the first authors pay special attention to situational and unfamiliar uses. Also note that there is no absolute consensus about the sub-classifications of the various uses.
T ables 1 (a and b) lists the anaphoric uses. Hawkins and Prince do not make any distinction among them. It is not clear whether Prince would consider the definite description in a sequence like he travelled... the journey as textually evoked, nor if Fraurud would consider that as subsequent mention. L?bner only refers explicitly to “direct anaphora”, those cases based on an antecedent with identical head. But what he calls pragmatic anaphoric seems to apply well for all examples in the table. L?bner says that the construction of a universe of discourse is comparable to the braiding of a complex multi-dimensional network, with object and event nodes; every node is a potential discourse referent, and anaphoric descriptions are used to refer to nodes in the net, usually providing only sortal information for the retrieval of their referent. Clark, on the other hand, distinguishes among four different ways in which a co-reference relation may be realised, but he is silent about the cases that Strand calls specification and widening. Sidner considers only two types of co-reference: identical head and generalization. Both Fraurud and Strand observe for a sequence like a man, a woman ... the couple a difference in the entities represented by the description and antecedent. Strand (1997) explains that events in his framework are represented by discourse referents and a link for cases like he travelled... the journey would be of the coreferentiality class. For named entities he explains that usually the relation is coreference, and the subclass specification or redescription. Clark and Strand give the most comprehensive account for the anaphoric use.
T ables 2 (a, b, c and d) summarises the classifications of associative uses and is the most complex of all. It is difficult to complete the table for each different author, since usually they are not explicit about all the possible associations capable of linking bridging descriptions with their anchors. Hawkins reckons the difficulty in providing the defining parameters for the set of possible associates; he then comments on the more general defining characteristics of these associations. He says that speaker and hearer share general knowledge of relationships between triggers and associates, usually part-of relations and attributes. It is not clear if he would consider event roles or cases involving hearers' supposition as associative anaphora.. Hawkins does not explicitly refer to a description as being associated to a previous VP, although this is considered in the examples of
anaphoric uses. Prince is not specific, either, about which are the possible associations between bridging descriptions and their anchors. She calls them all inferrables and says that “when a speaker evokes some entity in the discourse, it is often the case that s/he assumes that the hearer can infer the (discourse) existence of certain other entities, based on the speaker's beliefs about the hearers' beliefs and reasoning ability” (Prince, 1992 - page 304). Based on a general idea of “reasoning ability of speakers” I inferred that she would classify as inferrable all the examples in the table.
F raurud's first mention class seems to apply in general; exceptions are, perhaps, those uses classified by Clark as set-membership. L?bner says that associative anaphora are semantic FC2s with anaphoric arguments. He considers, in particular, those descriptions which have a relational noun (use), and whose argument is specified by an antecedent. Some of the associations exemplified in the table seem to be based on other grounds, however; such cases were indicated by question marks. Clark's account points to several distinct relations. His set-membership relation is classified as direct reference; all other relations listed under Clark in Table 2 are classified as indirect reference. Sidner's cases of associated specification descriptions correspond clearly to those explicitly referred by Hawkins and Prince as associative anaphoric and inferrable. It is not clear how broad her class of associated specification was meant to be, but we considered it to be very general; her inferred specification rule applies for those cases based on hearers′ suppositions. Clark's and Strand's classifications are the most detailed. Strand (1977) suggests that a causation link (a third subclass in the adjoining class) might be applied for the cases in which there is a relation of reason, cause and consequence. Strand does not classify optional roles (cases which involve hearers' suppositions) which are observed by Clark.
T he situational uses are presented in Tables 3 (a and b). Hawkins and L?bner agree that some cases refer directly to the physical context (pragmatic deictic, visible and immediate situation) whereas others (semantic FC2s with deictic argument and larger situation) only relate to the context, in the sense that their interpretation involves context identification and reasoning. Some uses may rely either on specific or general knowledge: in the example of a wedding situation, the interpretation of a description such as the bride may involve either specific knowledge of the referent or the general knowledge that weddings have brides. The same ambiguity is expressed in terms of situationally inferrable3 or unused in Prince's taxonomy. Fraurud also reckons that first mention uses may require situational anchors or referents, although she does not name different classes for them.
2These descriptions are not considered to be complemented with full relatives.
3Prince does not use this term herself but we explained it before.
I n Tables 4 (a and b) the description the colour red is given as unfamiliar by Hawkins but would probably fit better in Prince's unused. All but one unfamiliar use are semantic definites in L?bner's scheme. L?bner discriminates the woman Bill went out with from uses like the fact that... probably because in the first case the referent is just associated to another known entity, whereas in the latter the conceptual referent is determined by the complement (although both are based on complements which disambiguate a sortal head noun). Later in (L?bner 1996) he presents the book I gave you yesterday as an FC1 but he does not say whether he is considering it semantic or pragmatic. Note that the descriptions that illustrate situational and unfamiliar uses are potentially discourse new. However, nothing prevents them from being used in subsequent mention. Hawkins and L?bner give the most complete classifications for discourse new descriptions.
正在阅读:
A Review of the Linguistic Research on Definite Descriptions04-15
SMO和CRO的区别04-23
方案违背和方案偏离的定义、区别和处理09-03
热轧和冷轧的区别12-14
简易电子称设计报告01-10
对中国文化、美学、文艺的认识12-17
2012.1苏教版高二期末语文试卷09-01
BiPAP和BIPAP的区别12-22
律诗和绝句的区别07-22
- 教学能力大赛决赛获奖-教学实施报告-(完整图文版)
- 互联网+数据中心行业分析报告
- 2017上海杨浦区高三一模数学试题及答案
- 招商部差旅接待管理制度(4-25)
- 学生游玩安全注意事项
- 学生信息管理系统(文档模板供参考)
- 叉车门架有限元分析及系统设计
- 2014帮助残疾人志愿者服务情况记录
- 叶绿体中色素的提取和分离实验
- 中国食物成分表2020年最新权威完整改进版
- 推动国土资源领域生态文明建设
- 给水管道冲洗和消毒记录
- 计算机软件专业自我评价
- 高中数学必修1-5知识点归纳
- 2018-2022年中国第五代移动通信技术(5G)产业深度分析及发展前景研究报告发展趋势(目录)
- 生产车间巡查制度
- 2018版中国光热发电行业深度研究报告目录
- (通用)2019年中考数学总复习 第一章 第四节 数的开方与二次根式课件
- 2017_2018学年高中语文第二单元第4课说数课件粤教版
- 上市新药Lumateperone(卢美哌隆)合成检索总结报告
- Descriptions
- Linguistic
- Research
- Definite
- Review
- 【新版】苏教版五年级语文下册《晓出净慈寺送林子方》教案【名校
- 依法从严治军,条令永存我心
- 人教版八年级数学上册11.1 与三角形有关的线段考点练习(含答案)
- 2022年自考《室内设计》模拟试题及答案(卷二)
- 2022年河南工业大学新闻与传播学院440新闻与传播专业基础[专业硕
- 酒店管理导论论述餐饮经营的特点及其成本分析的意义
- Removed_中国哲学史2修改版31
- 个人年终工作总结报告
- 高效液相色谱法测定舒冠片中淫羊藿甙含量-精品
- 年产15000台节能变频器(柜)生产建设项目可行性研究报告
- 发电企业档案管理标准
- 文学社活动策划书.doc
- 房屋抵押的借款合同范本精华版
- 英语 七年级所给词的适当形式填空测试题及答案(1)
- 研究论文:试议私募投资基金发展及资本运作
- 本一年级语文下册口语交际“打电话”教案
- 精选学生自我鉴定汇总8篇
- 专题03 透镜-2022年中考物理试题分项版解析汇编(第01期)(原卷版)
- 幼儿园社会教育活动及设计考试试题与答案
- 长春市(全市)房地产投资情况数据分析报告2022版